Wat van plekke, rolle en ampte? Want die reg gaan oor meer as individuele regte

Show simple item record

dc.contributor.author Malan, Jacobus J. (Koos)
dc.date.accessioned 2022-03-08T10:52:09Z
dc.date.available 2022-03-08T10:52:09Z
dc.date.issued 2022-03
dc.description.abstract The notion of subjective individual human rights is presently occupying a dominant position in legal thinking and practice. Hence, people’s position within the legal order is almost exclusively conceptualised in terms of individual human rights – abstract, equal, universal subjective individual human rights – to put the concept in true perspective. Nothing, so it is believed, needs to be added to that. In our day, moreover, human rights assume the character of a redeeming gospel, guaranteeing justice comprehensively and serving as a panacea for all the challenges humanity might be facing. Whenever a new ill arises a new human right will surface providing the required cure. However, the dominance of human rights is no natural given. Its present dominance is also of fairly recent origin. It is associated with a distinctive individualist ideology that emerged only since early modernity. It made tumultuous strides during the revolutionary era in the last quarter of the eighteenth century and finally triumphed only after World War II. Given the tremendous upsurge of subjective individual rights, conceptualisation of law in its objective guise as a holistic system has largely been neglected. This is unfortunate, since it has caused a distorted and impoverished view of what law – and a legal order – on closer analysis should signify. The last part of the discussion (Part 4) precisely seeks to offer suggestions as to what law viewed from an objective vantage point should signify. To reach that point, an historical overview of the emergence of the concept of the individual is first given in part 2, followed in part 3 with an overview of the rise of individual rights. These two issues are closely inter-related. For clarity’s sake we deal with them separately. Focusing first on the individual (and individualism), it is shown that the “individual” of Classicism and the Middle Ages was in fact far removed from the individual of present-day individualism. Thus Louis Dumont (similar to Ernst Troeltsch, Alasdair MacIntyre, Collin Morris and various other idea historians referred to in Part 2) highlights the drastic break between the kind of individuality of early Christianity in stark contrast to contemporary individualism, explaining: Actually, the old form and the new are separated by a transformation so radical and so complex that it took at least seventeen centuries of Christian history to be completed, if indeed it is not continuing in our times. This “individual” was a sinner before God the Almighty, equal to all other individual sinners, yet “naturally” anchored in a variety of communal settings occupying designated places and fulfilling roles. The latter were not regarded as equal to all others and exercising individual rights on an equal footing with all other individuals. Only after the individualising events specifically associated with René Descartes and Thomas Hobbes, something that vaguely resembled the modern-day individual, reflecting the notion of individualism, really started emerging, culminating in the post World War II triumph of individualism. Part 3 deals with the equally modern-day notion of subjective individual human rights. Concurrent with abstracting the notion of the individual, the idea of individual rights appears to have emerged only in the nominalism of William of Ockham and others. Before that, none of the Classical roots of our Western civilisation – Christianity, Classical Athenian philosophy, Roman law – conceived of law as a system of subjective equal human rights. On the contrary, law was viewed in the first place as a natural whole designating specific places, roles and offices to each person. Thus Michael Oakeshott explains: This is the ‘well-ordered’ polis, the polis in which not only is each man doing what his special aptitude fits him to do, but in which, also, the proper hierarchy of faculties of the soul is preserved. Roman law with reference to numerous classical sources such as the work of Celsus and Paulus as reported in the Digest in the Justinian Code, as well as various others such as Marcus Aurelius all viewed law as an objective (cosmic) order of justice sustained by everyone fulfilling his and her (naturally) allocated, distinctive roles. Individual rights have no doubt brought about huge strides to the betterment of human existence, but such rights also have a dark downside, having caused an inordinate degree of fragmentation, atomism and loss of a sense of civilisation. It is suggested that our classical Western roots of civilisation may be of help not by simply transplanting them into our present-day reality but instead to regard them with hermeneutical judgment as argued by Danie Goosen. It is on the basis of this constructive relationship with our tradition, steering clear from the extremes of a reactionary retreat to classicism on the one hand as well as, on the other, a hostile rejection of anything that classicism might offer, that I embark on the discussion in Part 4. It is argued that over and above subjective individual rights we stand to gain richly from the following six notions for elucidating our insight into how a sound legal order should be conceived. These six notions, unpacked in the last part are that of place, role, office, capacity, responsibility and calling. en_ZA
dc.description.abstract Individuele regte, meer bepaald die denkbeeld van abstrakte, gelyke, universele, subjektiewe menseregte oorheers tans die regsdiskoers en -praktyk. Dit is egter van onlangse oorsprong, want hierdie denkbeeld het eers gedurende die rewolusionêre tydvak in die laaste kwart van die agtiende eeu sterk op die voorgrond getree en toe ná die Tweede Wêreldoorlog beslissend geseëvier. In hierdie bespreking word die opkoms van die individu eers nagegaan en daarna dié van individuele regte. Dit word gedoen met verwysing na die Klassieke Griekse denke, die klassieke Romeinse reg en die daaropvolgende Middeleeuse tradisie tot by die Vroeg-Moderne tydvak. In plaas daarvan dat die individu met (individuele) regte in ’n potensieel of daadwerklike verhouding van spanning met ander individue met soortgelyke (botsende) individuele regte as die wesenlike eienskap van die reg beskou is, is die reg eerder kosmies beskou, dit wil sê, as ’n objektiewe regsgeheel waarbinne mense uiteenlopende toegewese rolle vertolk het. By die beantwoording van die vraag of ons enigsins baat te vind het by hierdie pre-moderne beskouings is die uitgangspunt, in navolging van Danie Goosen, dat ons met hermeneutiese oordeel eerder as met dogmatiese drif te werk moet gaan. Daarvolgens word die uiterstes vermy om die klassieke denkbeelde óf heeltemal (progressiwisties) te verwerp óf dit reaksionêr op ons huidige werklikheid te probeer oorplant. Teen hierdie agtergrond word hier geredeneer dat die volgende ses denkbeelde wat verder in Deel 4 uitgepluis word, náás individuele regte ’n belangrike bydrae te lewer het tot ’n meer omvattende, realistiese en harmoniese begrip van wat die reg behoort te behels. Die denkbeelde is plek, rol, amp, hoedanigheid, verantwoordelikheid en roeping. en_ZA
dc.description.department Public Law en_ZA
dc.description.librarian hj2022 en_ZA
dc.description.uri http://tgwsak.co.za en_ZA
dc.identifier.citation Malan, Koos. Wat van plekke, rolle en ampte? Want die reg gaan oor meer as individuele regte. Tydskrif vir Geesteswetenskappe, Jaargang 62 No. 1: Maart 2022. doi.10.17159/2224-7912/2022/v62n1a3. en_ZA
dc.identifier.issn 0041-4751 (print)
dc.identifier.issn 2224-7912 (online)
dc.identifier.other 10.17159/2224-7912/2022/v62n1a3
dc.identifier.uri http://hdl.handle.net/2263/84385
dc.language.iso Afrikaans en_ZA
dc.publisher Suid Afrikaanse Akademie vir Wetenskap en Kuns en_ZA
dc.rights Suid Afrikaanse Akademie vir Wetenskap & Kuns en_ZA
dc.subject Abstract subjective individual rights en_ZA
dc.subject Abstrakte individuele regte en_ZA
dc.subject Christianity en_ZA
dc.subject Christendom en_ZA
dc.subject Classical Greek ideas en_ZA
dc.subject Griekse tradisie en_ZA
dc.subject Tradition en_ZA
dc.subject Denkbeelde en_ZA
dc.subject Roman law en_ZA
dc.subject Romeinse reg en_ZA
dc.subject Views en_ZA
dc.subject Opvatting en_ZA
dc.subject Jurists en_ZA
dc.subject Juriste en_ZA
dc.subject Law in an objective sense en_ZA
dc.subject Reg in die objektiewe sin en_ZA
dc.subject Law in the subjective sense en_ZA
dc.subject Reg in die subjektiewe sin en_ZA
dc.subject Plato en_ZA
dc.subject Aristotle en_ZA
dc.subject Hobbes en_ZA
dc.subject Nominalism en_ZA
dc.subject Nominalisme en_ZA
dc.subject William of Ockham en_ZA
dc.subject Willem van Ockham en_ZA
dc.subject Notions of place en_ZA
dc.subject Denkbeelde van plek en_ZA
dc.subject Notions of role en_ZA
dc.subject Denkbeelde van rol en_ZA
dc.subject Notions of office en_ZA
dc.subject Denkbeelde van amp en_ZA
dc.subject Notions of capacity en_ZA
dc.subject Denkbeelde van hoedanigheid en_ZA
dc.subject Notions of responsibility en_ZA
dc.subject Denkbeelde van verantwoordelikheid en_ZA
dc.subject Notions of calling en_ZA
dc.subject Denkbeelde van roeping en_ZA
dc.title Wat van plekke, rolle en ampte? Want die reg gaan oor meer as individuele regte en_ZA
dc.title.alternative What about places, roles and offices? Because the law is about more than individual rights en_ZA
dc.type Article en_ZA


Files in this item

This item appears in the following Collection(s)

Show simple item record