Renarrativizing Plato

Show simple item record

dc.contributor.author South African Society for Greek Philosophy and the Humanities
dc.contributor.author Wilkinson, Lisa Atwood
dc.date.accessioned 2009-10-19T06:53:35Z
dc.date.available 2009-10-19T06:53:35Z
dc.date.issued 2001
dc.description Appears in Phronimon, Volume 3 Number 2(2001) en_US
dc.description.abstract Postmodernism makes it difficult to maintain, among other things, that historical facts are discovered or found, that these 'facts', things like names, dates, places and events, somehow speak for themselves, although simple reflection should be enough to establish that, to echoe Richard Rorty, "the world does not speak, we do". It is we who speak for names, dates, places, and events, and in so doing, transform a meaningless sequence of letters or series of numbers into an historical person or epoch of some importanee. This process of speaking-for otherwise disparate 'facts' is called 'narrative' and narrative, as Roland Barthes once observed, seems to be "simply there like life itself . . . international, transhistorical, transcultural". But philosophy has also been presumed to be "international, transhistorical, transcultural" and "simply there like life itself," and philosophy is often thought to be a non-narrative form of language. Narrative is thought to deal with what is transitory, ephemeral, and contingent, what the Platonic Socrates calls the world of Becoming, while philosophy deals what persists through change, what is necessarily true. Philosophy's claim to be international, transhistorical, and transcultural is also a function of the "objects" it studies; indeed, philosophy often reads as if it were speaking for these objects, and not for the philosopher who is writing it. Thus does philosophy concern Reality or the world of Being, although the author to whom the distinction between Being and Becoming is usually attributed--Plato--wrote dialogues in which the speaking is done by characters and not by Being or Reality, nor for that matter, by Plato himself. Strangely, when Plato's dialogues are seen as philosophy they are typically not se en as dialogues; rather, the philosophy in the dialogues is identified with what Socrates--or in his absence, the Eleatic or Athenian Stranger--say plus what their statements logically imply. en
dc.description.uri http://explore.up.ac.za/record=b1411260 en_US
dc.format.extent 17 Pages en_US
dc.identifier.citation Wilkenson, LA 2001, 'Renarrativizing Plato', Phronimon, vol. 3, no. 2, pp. 237-253. en_US
dc.identifier.issn 1561-4018
dc.identifier.uri http://hdl.handle.net/2263/11488
dc.language.iso en en_US
dc.publisher South African Society for Greek Philosophy and the Humanities en_US
dc.rights South African Society for Greek Philosophy and the Humanities en_US
dc.subject Renarrativizing en
dc.subject Historical facts en
dc.subject Narrative en
dc.subject Speaking-for en
dc.subject.lcsh Plato -- Criticism and interpretation en
dc.subject.lcsh Postmodernism en
dc.subject.lcsh Philosophy en
dc.title Renarrativizing Plato en_US
dc.type Article en_US


Files in this item

This item appears in the following Collection(s)

Show simple item record